2018-2019 NHSEB Case 9: Picnic Nitpick

Randy notices 7-year-old Lisa dominating at the chess table. However, it’s quickly apparent that she’s no prodigy, but a hustler – moving pieces when no one is looking, making up rules to her advantage, and as a result winning the adulation of adult spectators unfamiliar with the game. He wonders whether to intervene, and if so, how.

My cutie pie Emily, who would never cheat at chess…

On the one hand, no money is at stake, and Randy doesn’t know anyone at this community picnic. It’s not like Lisa’s his niece or it’s his own children being unfairly beaten. On the other hand, there at least three things wrong with what’s happening.

First the losing kids are probably getting their feelings hurt. Some may be able to brush it off, but others may be in tears. We don’t know from the case details, but to the extent Lisa’s victims are visibly distraught, this would give Randy reason to say something.

Second, the longer Lisa gets away with her trickery, the more likely she’ll develop a deceptive, cheating personality, which may lead her to inflict future harms. Chess cheating today could lead to investment fraud tomorrow… Yet an effective correction could prove a pivotal moment in the development of a legendarily virtuous character – “Lisa the Just,” the philosophers would call her…

And third, not only are the kids being tricked, but so are the spectators. They wouldn’t praise Lisa if they knew she was cheating, and so are being deceived in a way that’s probably amplifying the embarrassment of the losers, as well as reinforcing Lisa’s propensity to deceive in the future.

Something should be done, and since Randy is the only person there besides Lisa who truly understands chess, he’s the guy to do it. But what?

Given that Lisa is only 7, his approach needs to be gentle. Were Lisa 30, Randy could be more direct. A 30-year-old could better handle directness emotionally, and even if they couldn’t, would be more blameworthy for their actions. Our capacities for reflection and moral reasoning aren’t fully developed when we’re young – this is why we have a juvenile criminal justice system with less harsh punishments for offenders under 18. Lisa has some understanding that what she’s doing is wrong. But at 7, she’s less sensitive to the impact of her actions on her peers, doesn’t fully appreciate why deception is wrong, or comprehend how her actions today will mold her character of tomorrow.

So Randy might simply say, “I’m sorry young lady, but a player only has to say ‘check’ when they’re attacking their opponent’s king. Being aware of whether your queen is in danger is each player’s responsibility – no verbal warning required.”

Or, “Wasn’t it the case that this rook was actually on this square? The wind must have slid it over.”

Randy might even use the opportunity to coach. Lisa obviously has the interest and some skill, and would probably prefer to win legitimately if she could.

“Might I suggest castling? Oh, you don’t know how to castle? Here, let me show you – this move helps protect your king, and frees your rook to go on the offensive.”

Whether Lisa is receptive to any of this will likely depend on the reasons driving her behavior. Maybe an older sibling tends to cheat her at the chess table, and she’s simply modeling their behavior. Or maybe the innocent-looking kids she’s beating were bullying her earlier, and she’s simply putting them in their place.

But whatever her motives, and whatever her response, something needs to be done, and the power disparity between Randy and Lisa (plus the fact that he’s a stranger) rule out a heavy-handed approach. Were his attempts to mold her in a more honest direction ineffective, Randy might consider consoling the kids she’s defeating, or offering to coach them.

Ethics Bowl and Democratic Deliberation

After more than six months of planning, in March of 2018 Bob and Joanne Ladenson moderated an “Ethics Bowl and Democratic Deliberation” panel discussion at the annual Association for Practical and Professional Ethics conference in Chicago. I was honored to be invited to chronicle that event.

Bob introducing the panel

Alluding to the devolving state of American civil discourse, Bob opened by remarking that the session “has a special urgency and immediacy” in 2018, a time when personal insults and disregard for history and facts have become routine at the highest levels. How did we get here?

Panelist Paula McAvoy from the University of Wisconsin argued that while American politics has always involved mudslinging, the watershed moment marking the beginning of the current decline was passage of the Voting Rights Act of 1965. This empowered the federal government to more forcefully intervene on the behalf of minorities, which disrupted the White-led status quo, undermining the gentlemen’s agreement the major parties had previously maintained, pushing Democrats further to the left and Republicans further to the right.

Dr. McAvoy went on to argue that growing income inequalities since the 80s exacerbated middle-class insecurity, which has driven resentment towards immigrants and racial tension.

In contrast, panelist Deborah Mower from the University of Mississippi offered the rise of political talk radio in the 90s, and its “valorization of righteous indignation” as a primary source of the current political environment. Not necessarily disagreeing, Dr. McAvoy added how Newt Gingrich led this approach initially via C-SPAN, positioning the Republicans as an “opposition party” with an uncompromising approach.

On ethics bowl as a partial antidote, Dr. McAvoy called the events “one of the best forms of ethics education I’ve ever seen,” and Dr. Mower touted how ethics bowl incentivizes engagement with people of opposing views both during preparation (so teams can come to an internal consensus), and during competition (to ensure a good score).

With benefits not limited to the competitors, Dr. Mower explained an innovative way her Intercollegiate Ethics Bowl team has expanded its influence – a “Great Debate” mock bowl that invited faculty, the broader student population, and even the local community to watch her team debate Mississippi’s celebration of April as Confederate Heritage Month. The crowd got an opportunity to witness spirited, yet respectful and intelligent discussion of a very controversial issue, and the team plans to hold a second event of the same sort, this time debating whether “the standard of consent for sexual relations should be an affirmative yes.”

Providing the perspective of an educator and bowl enthusiast at a school with a large Hispanic population, panelist Scott Dick, a teacher and ethics bowl coach from Chicago’s Pritzker College Prep High, explained some of the disadvantages underprivileged schools face. While some enjoy a dedicated philosophy class, his ethics team is only able to meet once per week, a problem especially common in public schools across the country.

On how to handle the sometimes silly and extreme views high school students entertain, such as eating the poor to stave off poverty, Mr. Dick recommended empathy and patience. “You have to engage at their level and play at their level.”

A panelist adding additional local context was Bart Schultz, author, longtime ethics bowl supporter, Senior Lecturer in the Humanities, and Executive Director of the Civic Knowledge Project at the University of Chicago. Among the programs Mr. Schultz oversees is Winning Words in which students lead discussions at south side Chicago inner city schools on philosophical topics including applied ethics. (For background on Mr. Shultz’s work on The New Chicago School of Philosophy click here.)

Mr. Schultz praised former Chicago Alderman Leon Despres for his ability to consistently discuss tough issues with respect and precision, and cited the work of Danielle Allen in asking how the ethics bowl format might be modified to even more effectively model and encourage respectful deliberation. One audience member suggested using questions that more intentionally steer teams in morally enlightening and fruitful directions.

With opening remarks from each of the panelists on the table, the group welcomed a friendly critique from an audience member that ethics bowls, with their emphasis on thoroughly appreciating various angles, may be creating “fence sitters” as opposed to committed advocates. The worry is that when citizens are aware of just how complex tough issues are, they’ll be less likely to confidently act.

Dr. McAvoy lent some support to the critique by citing studies that have shown that when citizens are presented with competing messages on an issue, voting rates actually decrease. Mr. Schultz agreed that “paralysis by analysis” could indeed be one result of learning too much about an issue once believed simple and clear.

However, Dr. Mower responded by arguing that activism and enlightenment are not mutually exclusive – that you can be a passionate activist and civil, thoughtful. And Mr. Dick argued that regardless of how thoroughly his high school ethics bowl team covered a given issue, his students never had a problem choosing and confidently arguing for a particular stance.

IEB organizer and former competitor Rachel Green offered a related worry: “Might ethics bowl suggest all views are equally good?”

Dr. Mower explained that it’s never the ethics bowl community’s intent to suggest ethics is a subjective matter, though ethics professors can attest that this is a common early response from students sometimes overwhelmed by competing, and seemingly equally strong positions for the first time.

Greg Wright, a professor and ethics bowl enthusiast from Utah, shared a specific issue he’d faced in teaching applied ethics generally – that of religious students sometimes being wary of philosophical ethics. It was suggested that Notre Dame philosopher Robert Audi’s basic argument – that Christ’s Golden Rule gives us good reason to think through public policy questions using reasons anyone can appreciate, regardless of their faith or lack thereof – is sometimes convincing, and worth giving a try.

Audi’s argument is essentially that if we desire to treat others as we would like to be treated, then we can’t base our laws on religious reasons alone. Were we to find ourselves in the religious minority, we wouldn’t want to be coerced by laws according to a faith we did not share. Studying philosophical ethics, and doing ethics bowl, are therefore ways to develop the capacity to reason through tough issues from a perspective anyone can appreciate, regardless of their faith or lack thereof.

Last, longtime IEB coach and bowl organizer Pat Croskery added commentary on ethics bowl’s contrast with debate – how he finds it reassuring that teams are able to acknowledge, absorb and reframe other teams’ positions, indicating genuine engagement and understanding, and providing hope for America’s political future, and for ethics bowl’s role in leading us in a more civil direction.

The Case Summary Matrix

Depending on your bowl organizer’s tastes, your team may need to prepare to discuss up to fifteen cases. That’s a lot of material – a lot of philosophical twists and turns, too.

One way to make it more manageable for your team is to develop a case summary matrix.

Customizing is allowed, but the basic idea is for each case to have a concise snapshot of:

  • Basic details (who, what, when, where, why)
  • Moral considerations (the key ones, from different directions)
  • The team’s view (in a nutshell, how they evaluated the case – answered the key study questions)

Getting that much on paper will make case coverage more manageable. But for an even more robust and complete matrix consider adding:

  • A possible objection (how someone might critique your team’s view)
  • A reply to that objection
  • Bonus points (anything relevant not included already, which may or may not arise during the judges’ Q&A portion)

If you’re a more heavy-handed coach, you can develop this matrix for your team. Or if, like me, you prefer to encourage your team to develop their own views, you can simply draw a blank table of the matrix on the board, fill in one or two as examples, and ask particular students fill in the rest.

This is a good way to get a team on the same page when the bowl is looming. But could also be used early in the season, and then revised as your bowl prep sessions play out.

Here’s a partially completed example that you’re welcome to download and edit, which I used with my own ethics bowl team during the 2017-2018 season. Enjoy!

Use Ethical Theory?

Some coaches take for granted that if their team understands Utilitarianism, Kantianism, Virtue Ethics, Feminist Care Ethics or some other ethical theory well enough to apply it, they should – the judges are sure to be impressed.

But there’s been backlash from bowl enthusiasts, judges among them, who worry sometimes ethics bowl becomes ethical theory bowl.

Teams get hung up on a favored theory and miss nuances a common-sense moral analysis would catch. Plus, no theory is immune from criticism, and many judges have their favorites. You train your team to apply consequentialism, then face a panel of deontologist judges! Not good.

This actually came up during a recent conversation with ethics bowl creator, Bob Ladenson.

 

Matt: Bob, you mentioned how witnessing so many ethics bowls has changed your views on moral philosophy.

Bob: Yes, I have much more openness and wiliness to consider views that are very different than my intellectual instincts tend to take me to.

An example is you know how in a match very often teams will approach an issue by examining it from the perspective of various ethical theories? At our summer ethics bowl workshop meetings this often receives strong criticism from philosophy professors who consider this a sort of shopping list, formulaic approach to ethics. And that’s the way I felt in the beginning – I thought it was kind of naïve what the students were doing.

But over the years I’ve come to appreciate what the students were doing, and often use that approach myself, and am much more open to looking at things from the perspective of a philosophy that might have fundamental issues.

Afterwards Bob shared a recent email exchange that helped clarify his view.

Bob: I regard major philosophical theories of ethics as immensely important conceptual resources for thinking about controversial, highly viewpoint dependent, hard to resolve ethical issues.  I don’t think though that they’re needed in each and every such case…

Truth to tell, however, I still don’t have a clearly worked out position with which I’m satisfied.  Temperamentally, like John Dewey, I’m partial to philosophical analyses that emphasize underlying commonalities in seemingly divergent viewpoints.

Thus… I stress that the attributes of open mindedness, readiness to engage in meaningful conversation about controversial ethical issues, and deliberative thoughtfulness, which all are indispensable for rigorous analytical thinking in applied ethics likewise qualify as virtues of ethical discourse.

 

Bob’s view seems to be that analyzing cases through the lens of ethical theory can be illuminating, but that this isn’t necessary. It’s far more important that your team approach the cases with the right attitude: “open mindedness, readiness to engage in meaningful conversation about controversial ethical issues, and deliberative thoughtfulness.”

I would tend to agree. But bottom line, will using ethical theory more likely help or harm your team come bowl day?

From my experience, using theory during bowl prep is almost always helpful, but whether your team should explicitly employ Utilitarianism or Feminist Care Ethics during the bowl itself depends on how they’re prepared to use them.

I’ve seen teams namedrop Kant without explaining how the Categorical Imperative works or clearly applying it to the case. This made them appear less competent than had they avoided Kantianism in the first place. I’ve also seen teams offer conflicting analyses of the same case from the perspective of multiple theories, with no suggestions on how to resolve the tension. Judges were visibly unimpressed.

Analyzing cases from the perspective of ethical theories during bowl prep can be a great way to clarify the morally relevant considerations, as well as what’s at stake and most important. This is because ethical theories are really just amplifications and logical defenses of moral considerations we already intuitively endorse.

  • Kantianism: rational consistency and respect for persons
  • Consequentialism/Utilitarianism: consequences/happiness
  • Feminist Care Ethics: the importance of relational ties, and how we should usually prioritize the interests of loved ones
  • Virtue Ethics: the relevance of how our actions reveal and shape our character

People naturally apply these same reasons to moral questions, and so will your team. The benefit of employing ethical theory during bowl prep is that this can help clarify, order and validate your team’s moral intuitions, which can sharpen and strengthen the arguments they present at the bowl.

If your team’s really good, they can even namedrop old Kant. Just make sure they’re ready to illustrate that universalizability test during the judges Q&A, should one of them request it.

But don’t take my word for it. What’s been your experience with ethical theory and ethics bowl? Overall helpful or harmful?

Coaching Between Rounds

As a high school ethics bowl coach, I’ve found that it’s between rounds one and two, and two and three, that a team will be most eager for and receptive to feedback – more malleable and open to modifying their approach. Once you get past round two, some fall into tacit roles, and their question response pattern becomes difficult to adjust.

Below is an example of feedback I provided my team between rounds 1 and 2 during a recent bowl in Tennessee. Notice how I emphasized both what they were doing well, and opportunities for improvement.

Last, know that sometimes no matter how clearly you convey your suggestions, teams will still forget to consider and respond to a possible objection, continue to say, “In our opinion…” and continue to go overboard in thanking the judges. All you can do is coach. How well the respond is largely on them.

Bob and Joanne Ladenson on Ethics Bowl’s Future

This article is based on an August, 2017 phone interview with Bob and Joanne Ladenson

As big as ethics bowl is today, creator Dr. Bob Ladenson remains the avuncular, soft-spoken phil prof the community loves and respects. Simply mention “Bob” to any ethics bowl organizer, intercollegiate through jr. high, and they’re likely to know exactly who you’re talking about, and just as likely to smile.

Bob’s principal collaborator, especially during the college bowl’s ramp up from isolated event to a formal two-tier structure, has been his wife, Joanne. Never heavy-handed, and always quick to share credit, the two have gently steered the initiative since its inception at Illinois Institute of Technology almost 25 years ago.

Now retired in California, I had the pleasure of chatting with Bob and Joanne on ethics bowl’s growth, how their view of its importance and benefits have changed over the years, and their thoughts on ethics bowl’s future.

Bob at 2013 National High School Ethics Bowl

Bob: When I quote “retired” – when I stepped down from being the head of the Ethics Bowl Executive Committee and Pat [Croskery] took over – I thought it was time. My dear friend and teacher Bernie Gert said, “The ethics bowl is like your child that’s grown up, and now it can go on its own.”

Going with the flow is too new-agey and breezy to put with my attitude. Rather, it’s like the ethics bowl is like my kids, who are adults. I hope it continues and flourishes.

The High School Ethics Bowl is really something. From the beginning I thought this would be great for high schools, but I could never figure out a way to move it forward. I was just delighted when Roberta [Israeloff] stepped up, for me out of the blue, and said this is something she wanted to work on developing.

Joanne: In terms of future directions to explore, if we can have tele-medicine, why can’t we have tele-ethics bowl?

Bob: At the Prindle Institute, for example, we have people who are much more technologically savvy than me and everyone in my generation. So maybe they’ll figure out a way to do this. My problem was that when we thought about doing it via media we could never keep the central objectives of ethics bowl intact.

Matt: That part of the future is actually here. I was involved in a brief webcam bowl a couple of years ago between high school teams in Tennessee, California, and Australia. The National High School Ethics Bowl has also held regional playoff rounds via Skype. I agree something’s lost when the teams and judges aren’t in the same room. But it’s less expensive and more convenient than traveling, with a lot of potential.

Joanne: I read a recent article in the Guardian about teenagers who use technology to communicate with their friends for everything… I’m thinking there might be some other ways to work with students not necessarily as a competition…

It’s critical for students to learn to listen, to respond respectfully, to find commonalities and areas of difference, to recognize that they may not always agree with each other but they can understand where the other person is coming from.

 

Indeed, these skills and attitudes are critical for the citizens of any successful democracy, and reason why Bob and Joanne’s contributions are so important.

We also discussed the apparent tension between ethics bowl’s competitive format and aim of fostering civility, how Bob and Joanne’s views on the appropriate role of ethical theory have changed as a result of witnessing so many bowls, and their thoughts on the source of the initiative’s sustained success.

Special thanks to Bob and Joanne for taking the time to chat, as well as for the gift of ethics bowl.

Version 2.0…

Welcome to EthicsBowl.org, version 2.0.

A hacker,  a bot, or some combination thereof infected critical files in February, 2018. (Way to go, hacker bots…) Hence, why the site was unavailable March and most of April, why some old articles are gone, and why the site is slightly redesigned.

The purpose remains the same — assist ethics bowl coaches who need and want the help, though I’ve decided to expand the target audience from high school ethics bowl coaches to ethics bowl coaches on any level. The more, the merrier, and maybe the various groups can benefit from one another’s expertise and company.  So expect analysis of IEB cases next season, of course along with NHSEB cases per the original version.

With the site’s aims in mind, should you have ideas on how to do it better, don’t be shy. Supporting ethics bowl is how I get my extra curricular philosophical kicks, and my primary outlet for bettering the world. So ideas welcome and appreciated. And if you’re inclined to submit a guest article, pitch away – it’s very likely I’d welcome the opportunity.

Thanks for visiting, and welcome to EthicsBowl.org, version 2.0.

 

 

2017-2018 NHSEB Case 15: The Sperm of the Dead

Amy and Bob plan a family. Bob dies. Amy asks doctors to extract and freeze Bob’s sperm.

Now Amy wants to use Bob’s sperm to conceive. Should she?

Such is the core question of case #15, just in time for Halloween.

One way to help your ethics bowl team think through cases where their moral intuitions are fuzzy is to consider similar cases where their moral intuitions are more clear.

What if rather than Bob’s sperm, Amy wanted one of his kidneys?

Were we considering whether Amy should be allowed to harvest one of Bob’s kidneys, we’d probably ask whether Bob signed an organ donor card, whether he’d ever expressed an interest in giving a kidney to Amy, and whether he’d made any concrete plans to carry out a transplant.

Were the answer to all three questions no, we’d probably deny Amy’s request. Sending Bob’s kidneys to the grave would in many ways a waste (he’s not using it anymore…), but our shared commitment to respecting one another’s bodily integrity usually continues even after death.

Were the answer to the first question yes but the second and third no, we’d either say Bob’s kidneys should go to whomever happened to be at the top of the organ transplant list, or that available organs should go to loved ones before strangers.

But to the extent that Bob had expressed an intent to donate a kidney to Amy in particular, and especially to the extent that he’d scheduled a transplant and taken steps to carry it out, we’d be more inclined to endorse doctors going ahead and transplanting one of his kidneys out of his dead body and into hers, even if he didn’t explicitly say this would be OK.

Your team might see this as reason to immediately approve Amy’s request to use Bob’s sperm to conceive. “They’d made plans to have a family, and even (say, for the sake of argument) bought a five bedroom home to make room for their kids. Just like it would be OK to take the kidney had plans been made and acted on pre-death, it would similarly be OK for Amy to take Bob’s sperm, right?”

However, a kidney has little value outside an organ system, and outside a person. But a sperm cell – a sperm cell can be conjoined with an egg to generate a completely new DNA sequence, which, if healthy and nurtured, will eventually become a full person. This seems a morally relevant difference requiring additional analysis.

What if Amy and Bob conceived only hours before Bob’s death?

Were we considering whether it would be permissible for Amy to carry full term had she been impregnated by Bob shortly before his death, we’d probably worry that she might struggle without Bob by her side, lament the tragedy that their child would never know their biological father, and worry about both Amy’s and the eventual child’s quality of life.

But we wouldn’t argue that Amy should have an abortion simply because Bob died. Bob dying might give Amy reason to consider an abortion, and were she to pursue one, regardless of our overall views on abortion ethics, we might say her actions are understandable, excusable, or even just.

But this is different from making a positive argument that Amy would somehow owe it to Bob to have an abortion. Were Bob to engage in presumably consensual sex before dying, allowing the resulting entity to grow and develop in Amy’s womb wouldn’t seem to violate any direct obligations she might have to respect his wishes. His consent to have sex would seem to imply a consent to also procreate, especially if no contraceptive measures were taken.

What if rather than his wife Amy, a stranger wanted to use Bob’s sperm?

In another illuminating twist, imagine that Sue sees Amy’s quest to conceive using Bob’s sperm on TV, and decides that if the doctors have sperm to spare, she’d like to birth Bob’s baby as well.

We’d say no, and we’d say no because whether, when and with whom we procreate is an intimate decision left to each individual to decide for themselves. We entertain Amy’s interest in conceiving due to her previous relationship with Bob, and Bob’s apparent desire and plans to have a child with her.

But Bob never even met Sue. We wouldn’t endorse Sue taking Bob’s sperm without his consent while he was alive. And we’re not going to endorse it after he’s dead, either. In fact, we’d protect Bob’s post-death sperm even more vehemently than his post-death kidneys.

The Primacy of Consent

Thinking through alternative scenarios like these should help your team realize the importance of consent in this case.

With the first alternative scenario, we concluded that whether Bob’s kidneys could be permissibly transplanted into Amy turned primarily on whether a) he’d signed up for organ donation, and b) whether he’d expressed interest in and made plans to donate a kidney to Amy in particular.

In the second alternative scenario, we concluded that if Amy conceived before Bob’s death, it would be fully permissible for her to birth and raise Bob’s child, even if Bob had never indicated this would be OK. The reason? In that case Bob would have voluntarily donated his sperm via consensual sex.

And in the third alternative scenario, we concluded that Sue, a stranger, had no moral claim to Bob’s sperm. Whether, when and with whom we procreate is a protected decision we allow people to make completely on their own. The reason we’re considering allowing Amy to use Bob’s sperm post-death is that Bob had planned to have kids with her. Without that connection to Bob’s plans and consent, Amy would have no standing.

We now know how to focus our analysis.

  • “What can we reasonably say about what Bob’s wishes would have been if he could have foreseen his death?”
  • “Would he have wanted to produce children with Amy regardless of whether he would have been around to help raise them?”

To the extent it’s reasonable to conclude Bob would have endorsed Amy using his sperm to procreate without him, doing so would seem permissible. But to the extent that it’s not reasonable to conclude as much, using his sperm would not be permissible.

What About the Family?

The case mentions that Bob’s broader family is uneasy about Amy’s desire to use his sperm post-death. But this just seems a distraction. If they have evidence that Bob wouldn’t want this (a note, recollection of a conversation, something on videotape), that would be relevant. But just because aunts and uncles might be creeped out isn’t reason enough to override whatever we’re able to conclude about what Bob himself would have wanted.

To see this, just ask how important it would have been for Bob to have received his family’s blessing before having kids with Amy had he lived. He’d of course have some obligation to consult with them, and all else equal, having the family on board is better than not. But it’s up to couples to decide whether to procreate on their own.

Bonus Scenario If You Dare!

What if Amy had become pregnant right before Bob died, but accidentally? Say they were in agreement on the desire to eventually have kids, and were in agreement on having sex, but on that day were using various contraceptives?

Contraceptive use is relevant because it suggests at that Bob did not fully consent to conceiving – that he was taking active steps to prevent it, in fact. However, he did consent to an activity he knew could lead to conception… Might the consent to have sex genuinely imply a consent to procreate?

A tough question, with implications for abortion ethics in particular. Were I writing bowl questions, this is exactly the sort I’d ask in a later round!