Just the Facts – NHSEB 2021-2022 Regionals Case 11 Guest Analysis

Another excellent analysis from our friend Coach Michael Andersen in Washington state, prepping his (very lucky) team for the Oregon High School Ethics Bowl. Thanks as always, Michael! And thanks to your team for sharing your superb coaching with the broader ethics bowl community.

Buenas dias, filosofos.  This week, with Case # 11 “Just the Facts,” we’re looking into the ethics of journalism, the desirability of objective reporting, and whether news organizations have an ethical duty to maintain a certain relationship to the general public.

Today’s Discussion Topic

  Do news organizations have an ethical duty to maintain a certain relationship to the general public? 

 If so, what is the nature of that relationship? 

 What, if any, is the value of objectivity in journalism?

Pre-Discussion Resources
  • (Video) “How to choose your news – Damon Brown” @ TedEd  (6-4-14). “How do we choose which news to consume? Get the scoop on how opinions and facts affect the news and how to tell them apart.” [4:48] 
  • (Video) “How Journalists Minimize Bias@ Facing History.org  (6-4-14).  “Journalists discuss the idea of bias and explain the processes they follow to combat bias in their reporting.” [6:31, Transcript PDF]

NHSEB Regional Ethics Bowl #11. Just the Facts

Mr. A’s Coaching Tips on This Case
  • What is the moral question?  What makes this an ethical issue? 

Grasping the moral dimension of this case may require you to step back and look at the broader picture of the journalism profession—it’s history here in America (and elsewhere), and especially with recent trends toward sensationalism, bias, corporate influence, and political polarization in news reporting. Surely, citizens of a democracy should care about whether the journalism they rely on for a healthy participation in government, or in other areas of social life, offers a quality (accurate, insightful) or shoddy (distorting, manipulative) view on the wider world.  We have a shared interest in this project of improving journalism standards, either indirectly through our consumer habits (i.e., which news outlets we pay for or routinely tune in to) or more directly (e.g., through letters to the editor, calling in to radio shows, lobbying for stricter legislation governing news outlets, etc.).  

The goal of robust objectivity or neutrality standards for professional news outlets is a moral issue because we need to trust these sources of information, and their reputation matters for their own sense of integrity, as well as our collective perception of it.  (After all, journalists are people too, and they presumably care about the quality of the work they do, which provides them a meaningful sense that their work is worthwhile.  Likewise, as citizens our sense of consulting the news to be informed must produce a feeling that such activity is worthwhile, and that the alternative—ignorance and apathy—is a worse option for us all.  These ethical sources of meaning depend on the aforementioned standards of journalistic professionalism, since such standards provide the foundation of our trust that a news outlet’s reporting activity will result in truthful, insightful news.)  So, consider trust and integrity as moral compass points that shape most people’s moral intuitions about the credibility of news outlets and the role they play in forming public opinion.

Clearly, Q1 refers to the “ethical duty” that news organizations owe to the general public, and Q3 inquires about “the value of objectivity”; so the case authors are obviously encouraging you to consider what is at stake morally for the parties involved (and more broadly for our society’s regard for the role the Press in a vibrant democracy).  The case description notes how editors either fired, restricted, or banned these reporters when and where their personal histories with the topics reported on were seen to jeopardize the perceived integrity of the news organizations employing them.  Given the reporters’ public history with these controversial topics (deemed a source of bias that compromised the objectivity and neutrality of their reporting), were these reactions by the news outlets warranted, in your team’s opinion?  Or would an alternative approach to the situation be more morally defensible?  

Consider too how trust and integrity are in tension with the value of fairness (as a form of justice)Fairness (as a form of justice) seems like an obvious moral concern for those sympathetic to the reporters’ perspective—since they clearly feel that their jobs and reputations were unfairly sacrificed “to protect the objectivity and neutrality of the reporting in question” (or at least the public’s perception of these ideals).  If these reactions by their employers were indeed unjustly discriminatory, then fairness (as a form of justice) would be the anchor moral concept of any argument explaining that position.  An interesting and parallel point here: one might also argue that trust and integrity go both ways: that the leaders of news outlets have a duty within their organizations to maintain an atmosphere of trust and integrity among their corps of reporters, since they won’t attract quality talent for long if these virtues are lacking in their day-to-day operations.  Discuss with your team if an ideal balance of these values—trust, integrity and fairness—is achievable to arrive at the most morally defensible handling of these situations when they arise.

Maybe the goal of a robust journalism ethics can take cues from the field of law?  Lawyers and judges typically recuse themselves from cases where they have a personal connection to the defendant or conflict of interest in the case’s outcome.  A standard set of courtroom protocols ensures that these lawyers or judges are properly vetted from the procedures governing such cases, thereby maintaining credibility of the justice system as a whole (well, in theory at least).  Should all journalists similarly recuse themselves from reporting on topics about which they exhibit a strong personal investment?  How would such potential conflicts of interest be reliably determined, and what threshold of a reporter’s “personal investment” would necessitate recusal?  Is their editor’s judgment sufficient?  Is there a similar concern for the editors’ own biases?  Some might view such a system of journalistic recusal as unnecessary to ensure “objective reporting.”  After all, reporting on a controversial story isn’t quite the same as serving as a lawyer or judge in a criminal case, they might claim.  What do you think?  Are there common standards of practice for reporters that could be instituted to allow them to report on an issue, even though the reporter in question has strong personal convictions or personal history related to the topic?

An intriguing sidebar issue in philosophy, sociology and psychology is whether the ideals of objectivity and neutrality that govern most professional investigative sciences or practices can, in fact, present a distorting—rather than reliable—picture of reality.  When such investigations involve social and personal realities (like political injustice, racism or sexism) charged with strong emotional content and subjective experience, the ideal of extracting one’s point of view from the messy details of life to that of a neutral spectator, removed and non-committed to the phenomena at hand, strikes many critics as outdated.  [See Resources #2 and #6 below for more details.] 

A fourth value (or virtue) is mentioned in the case description worth deliberating on: “What is better, say critics of objectivity, is to report the facts while also acknowledging one’s (limited and biased) point of view.  This is a sign of humility, and it may also have the benefit of opening up more ethical reporting standards.”  How, if at all, should humility play a role in moderating decisions about a news organization’s attempts to strive for objectivity—and thereby attain not just a semblance of institutional integrity but a genuine form of it?  Can a set of journalism protocols be developed that emphasizes (and balances) all four of these values?  Clarifying and instituting such a balanced set of guidelines could then inform day-to-day reporting practices, resulting in a more robust safeguarding of the news organization’s perceived worth, both externally and internally.  (Of course, there remains the problem of clarifying what humility (or any other virtue) in reporting and editorial oversight actually looks like in practice.  Is such a virtue-based goal realistic?)  

What do you think?  Are there other moral values (virtues) or principles that are relevant to answering Discussion Qs 1-3?  I’ve emphasized here a kind of Virtue Ethics approach, but maybe there’s a Deontological or Consequentialist view of the the moral tensions raised by Case #11.  Maybe it’s convincing to emphasize the rights due to the reporters here (although I tend to agree with Prof. Deaton about why rights-based appeals can be problematic).  Maybe there’s an ideal balancing of interests of the parties involved that would somehow maximize happiness, perceived welfare or preference satisfaction.  Good luck in your investigations!

Helpful (But Optional) Resources for Further Study:
  1. (Resource) “Current Topics: An Undergraduate Research Guide : Fake News. @ Univ. of Wisconsin-Madison Libraries.  ”This research guide provides information on recognizing fake news articles and websites, fact-checking, and researching fake news.”  EDITOR’S NOTE: This is a superb resource!  Bookmark it on your home + Chrome browser, and make sure that you study the definitions of “bias” (both “explicit bias” and “implicit bias”).
  1. (Video)  “Should Journalism Be Objective? Serial: Part 2.” @ Idea Channel | PBS Digital Studios. Jan 28, 2015. “Welcome to PART DEUX of our discussion of “Serial”, the insanely popular podcast hosted by Sarah Koenig.  Last week we discussed objectivity in the law, and this week we’re turning our attention to objectivity in journalism.  Journalists have been tasked with objective reporting for decades, but is that a realistic goal?  Can any journalist be TRUELY objective? [12:18]  NOTE: The theme of transparency vs. objectivity in journalism is briefly outlined in this related lecture excerpt: “Jorge Ramos on Objectivity & Neutrality in Reporting.” [1:59]
  1. (Article)  “Why journalism is shifting away from ‘objectivity’.” @ The Christian Science Monitor. July 6, 2017. By Harry Bruinius. “Amid the unusual pressures of the Trump era, some are advocating a more interpretive or even combative approach to journalism – and argue that it will do more to help society.” 
  1. (Video)  “Unprecedented attacks and distrust for the media? History says no..” @ The Christian Science Monitor. June 23, 2017. “The president’s attacks on the media and the public’s mistrust for it are nothing new. Decades-long trends have set the stage for them.” [8:34]
  1. (Video) “Objectivity and Truth in Journalism: Is It Possible?” @ FORA.tv (Dec 24, 2012). “Scott Lettieri, news reporter for KGO radio, speculates whether an objective truth exists in journalism. Acknowledging that journalists strive for complete and absolute truth, Lettieri declares that citizens should synthesize all avenues of media and news to find it.” [3:37] POSSIBLE TRIGGER WARNING: The journalist interviewed here briefly (and non-graphically) recounts a story of a woman who was kidnapped, raped, and had become a victim of sex trafficking.  Some students might find this brief account disturbing. 
  1. (Video) “Objective vs Subjective (Philosophical Distinction) @ Carneades.org (7-10-16) “An explanation of the difference between objective and subjective, and definitions of each of these terms.  How can you tell if something is objective or subjective?  If a tree falls in the forest and no one hears it, does it make a sound?” [5:31] EDITOR’S NOTE: Like many ethical topics, the moral dimension of this case intersects with other areas of philosophy—here, the epistemology and metaphysics related to knowing and discerning whether the ideal of journalistic objectivity is something properly categorized as subjective or objective.  Without going down a rabbit hole too far, you should know that these sidebar topics will come up in the dispute about whether a news organization can trust a reporter (a subject), plus the editorial oversight process, to reliably maintain sufficient psychological distance from the topic reported on (presumably about which the reporter has some kind of personal investment).  Are reporters reliably capable of the mental discipline needed to meet objectivity standards, and thereby ensure credibility of the news organization with the public?  What kind of objectivity are we talking about?  (Surely, journalism isn’t a science, where the objects of study remain consistent enough in time and space to render “objective” findings.)  Is the ideal of objectivity in journalism even attainable for human reporters?  (I.e., cue the pessimist’s view that “It’s ALL subjective; objectivity doesn’t exist!” )   …I think you get the picture.  I recommend a practical lens when considering these questions.  A pure objectivity for the human sciences or for professions like journalism may not be possible; nevertheless, the aim of objectivity might be practically necessary to differentiate quality from shoddy journalistic practice.
  1. (Video)  “Real News vs. Fake News.” @ Univ of Louisville Research Assistance & Instruction. Jun 19, 2020. “Citizen Literacy is an online toolkit that promotes the development of key information skills for democratic citizenship and features short videos, handouts, and activities that faculty across all disciplines can integrate into their courses and assignments.” 
  1. (Video) “How to Spot Fake News – FactCheck.org@ FactCheck. “Fake news is nothing new. But bogus stories can reach more people more quickly via social media than what good old-fashioned viral emails could accomplish in years past.” [3:22] 
  1. (Article) “How Implicit Bias Works in Journalism” @ Nieman Reports. By Issac J. Bailey, Nov. 13, 2018. “Avoiding the pitfalls of hidden biases can lead to better story selection and more inclusive reporting. …A commitment to addressing implicit bias—an automatic or unconscious tendency to associate particular characteristics with particular groups—in news coverage could improve and transform audience engagement, increase trust, and lead to more accurate coverage depicting our increasingly diverse world.”
  1. (Article + Video) “The Unbiased Media: Are Journalistic Ethics Overriding Human Ethics? |  How to Survive in a World Accustomed to Fear” @ Big Think. (9-1-16) “Recent research in psychology reveals insights into how the stories we are exposed to affect our identities and ideas. What implications does this hold for the influence of the news and the ethics of journalism?” [7:57]
  1. (Resource) “Media Bias Ratings@ AllSides Media. “Everyone is biased — and that’s okay. But hidden media bias misleads, manipulates and divides us. AllSides Media Bias Ratings™ make media bias transparent, helping you to easily identify different perspectives so you can get the full picture and think for yourself.”
  1. (Video) “Political media’s bias, in a single chart@ Newsy.  (Dec 28, 2018) “Vanessa Otero set out to rank an ever-growing partisan media landscape, with the belief that an informed public is a better public.”  [4:26]
  1. (Video) “Confirmation Bias | Ethics Defined” @ McCombs School of Business. (Jan 28, 2021) “Confirmation bias is the tendency of people’s minds to seek out information that supports the views they already hold. It also leads people to interpret evidence in ways that support their pre-existing beliefs, expectations, or hypotheses.” [2:20]
  1. (Resource + Video) “What Is Bias? | Why Do Our Brains Love Fake News? | The Backfire Effect” @  Flathead Valley Community College – LibGuides – Evaluating Sources – Dealing with Bias
  1. (Article) “The lost meaning of ‘objectivity’.” @ American Press Institute “This guide, like many of the others in API’s Journalism Essentials section, is largely based on the research and teachings of the Committee of Concerned Journalists — a consortium of reporters, editors, producers, publishers, owners and academics that for 10 years facilitated a discussion among thousands of journalists about what they did, how they did it, and why it was important. The author, Walter Dean, was CCJ training director and API Executive Director Tom Rosenstiel formerly co-chaired the committee.”

Related Ethics Bowl Cases:

  1. 2015-16 Regional HSE201B Case #8. Reporting on a Scandal: “The editor of the high school’s newspaper learns that a community service group has not functioned according to school rules: they awarded service hours in exchange for money raised.  The leader of the club expresses regret and asks the editor not to publish the allegations because they will hurt his chances of college admission.  How should the editor weigh her journalistic responsibilities against a student’s right to privacy?” 

2. 2016-17 National HSEB Case #14. Responsibility for implicit bias: “Should we blame people for having or acting on implicit biases, and if so how much?  How should the fact that implicit biases are so widespread influence what we think about them?

3. 2016-17 National HSE201B Case #7. Teaching all sides: “Should a high school teacher in a class that studies many controversial subjects teach all sides of every issue or favor some sides over others?  Should she use her own judgement, teach all sides of public opinion, or defer to experts and scientists?  What questions can she treat as open and what questions should she teach as closed?” 

Boy, Bye: Or, On the Ethics of Ghosting – NHSEB 2021-2022 Regionals Case 3 Guest Analysis

The following guest analysis is by Michael Andersen, longtime ethics bowl supporter, Ethics Club Adviser at Vancouver School of Arts & Academics, Vancouver, WA, and regular EthicsBowl.org contributor. Thank you once again, Michael, for your superb analysis! This is actually from a PDF Michael created for his team, and is an excellent example of engaging a team before a coaching session, and leaving them with ample resources for further reflection. And sharing it publicly during the season is also a wonderful example of putting collaboration before competition. The spirit of the ethics bowl is strong with this one!

Good morning, philosophers. I hope that you had a restful Thanksgiving Break. Our case for discussion this week will be Case #3. “Boy, Bye: Or, On the Ethics of Ghosting” — a fictional one (but based in a realistic scenario) involving the ethics of ghosting via dating apps, as well as the gender norms and dynamics that sometimes affect the way individuals approach online dating.  I’ve uploaded the case session PDF below, and please read the case and the Discussion Qs therein.  Also, this week I’ve started a mini-section in the PDF called “Mr. A’s Coaching Tips on This Case” in which I try to help you think about the central moral dimension involved–the answer to the questions What is the moral question?  What makes this an ethical issue?  You might also find useful the two (optional) PSU Ethics Bowl videos “Care Ethics for Ethics Bowl” and “Virtue Ethics for Ethics Bowl,” both of which present moral frameworks that seem relevant to this case.  Check them out if you have time.

BONUS: Some of you might want to see another example of an Ethics Bowl round.  If so, I’ve linked below the Championship Match of the 2021 National High School Ethics Bowl, between Kent Place High School (NJ) and University High School (CA).  The first half of the round discusses case #8 “Killer Art” (see National Case set link below), and the Moderator’s Q appears on screen @ min. 4:21.  The second half (beginning @ min. 43:05) discusses case #10 “Do You See What I See?”, and the Moderator’s Q appears on screen @ min. 43:31.

Today’s Discussion Topic 

  Are there times it’s permissible to ghost?  Or is it permissible for some people to ghost, even if it’s not okay for others to do the same?

 How do gender norms and dynamics affect the way that individuals should approach dating? 

 Do the same rules apply to everyone?  Or is it permissible for some people to behave in certain ways while it would be impermissible for others to do the same?

Pre-Discussion Resources
  • (Video) “What Psychologists Can Tell You About Ghosting” @ SciShow Psych  (6-24-19). “Ghosting is when someone terminates a relationship by ending communications abruptly and without explanation.  Whether or not you’d consider ghosting someone might have a lot to do with how you view relationships in general.” [11:08] 

NHSEB Regional Ethics Bowl #3. Boy, Bye: Or, On the Ethics of Ghosting

Mr. A’s Coaching Tips on This Case

What is the moral question?  What makes this an ethical issue? 

Consider respect and dignity as two common moral intuitions at play in a dating encounter (whether it’s the initial or a follow up encounter), but these often conflict with a moral principle of autonomy—i.e., the right or condition of self-government.  In the modern world (at least in many cultures), we reserve the right to decide for ourselves who we will date, for how long, and under what circumstances.  What respect and dignity obligations do we owe to people in a dating situation?  Shouldn’t there be some limits to our exercising of our personal autonomy in dating situations?  In a face-to-face encounter, assuming we desire to end the option to date, and also assuming that one’s immediate safety isn’t at stake, most people would probably assume a minimum standard of basic decency is necessary.  That is, unless the person under consideration is behaving abusively or in a rude manner, that person deserves a basic standard of respect and dignity in the way we turn down their offer(s) to date.  

We’re all human, after all, and maintaining a climate of respect and dignity for all ensures more healthy social relations for everyone.  In the context of a prospective date, simply dismissing or ignoring a person in a face-to-face encounter might be tolerated in some social circles, but it’s hardly admirable, as it results in people feeling disrespected and their dignity as a person violated.  If only for the practical reason that others might treat us disrespectfully, many see a basic standard of respect and dignity as a reciprocal duty we owe to each other to make society work, and to make dating even possible.  (If everyone ghosted prospective dates regularly, then no one would take the risk to date.)  In the case description, Imani reflects that “She’s been ghosted before and it sucks.  It usually leaves her wondering if she did anything wrong or if she’s an interesting person to talk to.”  

Immanuel Kant convincingly argued that “…all and only persons (i.e., rational autonomous agents) and the moral law they autonomously legislate are appropriate objects of the morally most significant attitude of respect.  Although honor, esteem, and prudential regard played important roles in moral and political theories before him, Kant … put respect for persons, including oneself as a person, at the very center of moral theory, and his insistence that persons are ends in themselves with an absolute dignity who must always be respected has become a core ideal of [modern morality].” (“Respect@ Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.)

If the technology of dating apps makes it convenient for us to get into the habit of ghosting other people whenever the whim strikes us, then what kind of people are we likely to become?  What kind of dating culture is likely to evolve where this becomes the norm?  Maybe Imani in the passage quoted above is hinting not just at respect and dignity due to other persons but also a kind of self-respect, since whether or not she ghosts the men she might be interested in implies that getting into the habit of doing so reflects on her self image.  Perhaps, she thinks, “I don’t want to be the kind of person who dismisses people this way” or “Will I respect myself if I’m habitually leaving prospective dates in the dark about my intentions, even if it’s convenient in the moment?”

Context, of course, matters a lot here.  For Imani, while some online chat on the dating app has involved men who are “…demeaning or make inappropriate jokes, [and] some send unsolicited explicit pictures, [while] some just talk about themselves and don’t think to ask her any questions; …on the other hand, there’s three people she can think of who seemed really kind and thoughtful, and she can see herself interested in people like them in the future.”  If these latter people—who likely will have feelings of rejection or uncertainty similar to Imani’s—are ghosted by her just like the men who behave rudely or selfishly, then in effect it’s her need for convenience that reduces all of the prospective dates to candidates for ghosting (as Jake suggests).  Why should the convenient means (the technology) justify these harmful ends (a dismissal of basic respect and dignity due to the real person on the receiving end)?

Perhaps you might think that, for practical reasons, the sheer scale of options available to users of a dating app doesn’t realistically allow for one to engage with others as we would face-to-face.  That’s the benefit of the app’s architecture, no?  It’s like a digital version of a speed dating session with built-in match-making filtering, without the hassles of face-to-face pleasantries; and it facilitates remote communication without having to struggle through the energy-draining, risky exchanges that a face-to-face breakup would entail.  These features enhance our autonomy and make it more likely that users’ preferences are matched and met (thereby making loneliness less likely and potential happiness in relationships more possible). 

…But is that really what happens?  This might not be the first (or last) technology whose initial promises for increased well-being turn out to be hollow in many cases.  Perhaps dating apps, because of the way their architecture is designed, in the long run actually promote selfishness and/or rude treatment of others (much like the anonymity of other online platforms ends up making trollish behavior more common).  If the moral value of autonomy is to rank highly in our moral deliberations, the quality of self-governance involved should matter, not just the assertion of one’s entitlement to it.  If we govern ourselves poorly, selfishly, without regard for the dignity or respect of others, then our self-governance won’t matter much to others.  This means that respect for the autonomy of others (and ourselves) depends on a mutually-reinforcing network of persons continuing to treat each other with dignity and respect. If any technology platform erodes our ability to offer this to each other, then shouldn’t we turn a skeptical eye to the harmful norms propagated by that platform?  (Put simply, if dating apps make it easy to ghost other people, then it’s likely that users of those apps will make ghosting a habit—which, ironically, will make dating harder for everyone.)

What do you think?  Are there other values (or virtues) relevant to this case, besides autonomy, respect and dignity?  Are there principles like the Golden Rule (Do unto others as you would have them do unto you) that ought to govern our dating interactions, even online?  Naming these relevant moral values or principles—especially if they’re in conflict or tension—will help your team correctly identify what is the moral question of case #3, as well as to respond to questions about what the central (most important) moral dimension of the case is.  Once you name them, cited by evidence from the case description, discuss which values or principles deserve priority in answering the case’s Discussion Questions. 

Helpful (But Optional) Resources for Further Study
  1. (Video) “PHILOSOPHY – The Good Life: Kant @ Wireless Philosophy. “In this Wireless Philosophy video, Chris Surprenant (University of New Orleans) discusses the account of human well-being and the good life presented by Immanuel Kant in the his moral, political, and religious writings. He explains why Kant believes that the highest good for a human being is the conjunction of happiness and complete virtue and how it is possible for an individual to attain these two things at the same time.” [5:53] 
  1. (Article)  “Why I ghosted my best friend | My behaviour haunts me to this day.” @ BBC 3. By Anonymous. 22 October 2018.  EDITOR’S NOTE: While this article involves online ghosting of a friendship and not dating, the subjects involved experience related ethical complications as with case #3 (e.g., the way technology mediates their exchanges, likely with a sense of alienating remoteness and the lack of emotional cues or accountability that would come through face-to-face interaction).  The way that dating apps allow for an experience of convenient sorting and editing one’s communication with potential dates, as well as shields of anonymity and cultivated profiles, mirrors—in some respects at least—the manner in which friendships can be mediated in novel ways with online communication tools (in this case texting).  It’s worth exploring how these technologies are conflicting with, perhaps even reshaping, our deep social instincts about emotional responsibility (and thereby our ethical codes) in intimate relationships.  Is this author’s ghosting of her (former) friend comparable to Imani or Jake’s choices to ghost potential dates?  If so, how are the situations similar?  Which moral intuitions are at play in either context—online dating or online navigation of friendships? 
  1. (Article) “I’m a serial ‘ghoster’ in dating — here’s why I do it. @ Business Insider.  By James Lindsay, Jun 4, 2018. EDITOR’S NOTE: Maybe I’m old fashioned, but this article offers a testimony about ghosting in online dating that I—personally—find problematic, yet the author does articulate how online dating can transform our sense of personal responsibility, normalizing (rationalizing?) ghosting behaviors that wouldn’t be acceptable in person. Sample: “Within the confines of a common social group, dating, no matter how casual, always required a certain decorum. If you didn’t want to keep seeing someone, you had to say so, because you were definitely going to see that person again. Online dating has no such confines.“
  1. (Article) “Dating dilemma: is ghosting ever okay” @ THIS | Deakin Univ. Dr Petra Brown, Teaching Scholar, Faculty of Arts and Education, Deakin University.  Retrieved 11/29/21.
  1. (Article) “The Ethics of ‘Ghosting’@ Ethics Sage.  By Dr. Steven Mintz, PhD, is a professor emeritus from Cal Poly State University in San Luis Obispo.  09/04/2018.  
  1. (Article) “Pulling the sheet back on ‘ghosting’@ ASU Now. “ASU Now consulted Maura Priest, an associate professor and bioethicist in the School of Historical, Philosophical, and Religious Studies and the author of the forthcoming book, The Ethics of Dating, to explain the how and the why of this phenomenon.”  09/20/2019.
  1. (Article) “In Defense of Ghosting” @ Medium. By Reese Weatherl, Dec 25, 2020.
  1. (Scholarly Article) “ Psychological Correlates of Ghosting and Breadcrumbing Experiences: A Preliminary Study among Adults” @  International Journal of Environmental Research and Public Health. By Navarro R, Larrañaga E, Yubero S, Víllora B… 2020; 17(3):1116. https://doi.org/10.3390/ijerph17031116.
Related Ethics Bowl Cases

2017-18 National HSE201B Case #16. Haunted by Tinder: “What values are at play when determining how we should interact with people we meet through online dating platforms?  When, if ever, is ghosting someone on social media ever acceptable?”” 

2018-19 National HSEB Case #15. It’s Just a Preference: “Jason was recently encouraged by his friends to try online dating. After a few days of no hits, he finally matches with someone only for them to send a message saying, “Sorry, accidentally swiped right. Not into Asians”. While racial preferences seem to be common in online dating many claim that these trends in dating preferences are racist. Others argue that desire is deeply rooted and one shouldn’t feel obligated to go against it.  To what extent are racial preferences in dating an individual character flaw?  A broader social problem?  Neither?  Both?

NHSEB Case Roundtable Workshop Next Saturday

Our friends at NHSEB Academy are hosting a Zoom-based case discussion workshop next Saturday, December 4th at 4:30 EST.

Organized and led by philosophy students taking UNC’s Ethics Bowl and Democratic Deliberation class, coaches and teams will be invited to kindly and cooperatively think through cases 4, 7, 9 and 15:

  • Suffering in the Wild
  • 23 & Memaw
  • Priorities, Priorities…
  • All Eyes on You

Absent judges, score sheets, rankings and awards, this should be a wonderful opportunity to consider these cool issues in good faith. And with many bright moral thinkers in attendance, it should be a simple way to elevate our collective understanding… and also give your team an edge 😉

Registration is quick and easy at nhsebacademy.org/event-reg. I’ll be there. Hope to see you as well!

Art with an Asterisk – NHSEB 2021-2022 Regionals Case 8 Guest Analysis

The following guest analysis is by Michael Andersen, longtime ethics bowl supporter, EthicsBowl.org friend, and Ethics Club Adviser at Vancouver School of Arts & Academics, Vancouver, WA. Thank you, Michael, for sharing this superb analysis!

Case #8 from the 2021-22 NHSEB Regional Case Set, “Art with an Asterisk,” raises some thorny questions about the hazy territory between art and morality.  Question 1 (Q-1) asks, If it is possible to celebrate the art without excusing the transgressions of the artist, what form should that celebration take?  If it is not, what becomes of the art?  To begin grappling with this question, it is worth exploring what a “celebration”of artworks by a morally compromised artist might entail, as well as what “excusing” the transgressions of the artist suggests.  So, a necessary first step in drafting a coherent position on the question requires that you clearly define these operative terms in the Discussion Questions.

Does a “celebration” mean highlighting the artwork’s qualities in a museum display, theater brochure, album notes (or the like) in what could be characterized as a ‘whitewashed’ and neutral space, where nothing is mentioned about the artist’s (alleged) immoral and/or criminal conduct?  Or, on the other extreme, should sufficient biographical detail about such transgressions be foregrounded in all publications associated with the artworks in question?  There’s an array of possibilities here for “celebrating” artwork, ranging from: a) no mention at all of the controversy surrounding the artist; to b) including relatively minor qualifying footnotes about the artist’s problematic conduct; to c) a forthright spotlighting of the artwork’s “tainted” nature due to its association with a morally compromised creator; to d) refusing to showcase the work at all, but otherwise acknowledging the influence of the artist’s work in some less public format—which could also serve the purpose of financial divestment in the artist’s career or estate.  (The issue of morally-compromised artists, or their patrons, continuing to profit from their work strikes many as a key factor in this question.  This concern is especially relevant when, in spite of the seriousness of their transgression(s), artists or their patrons profit from the misconduct scandal itself.) 

These forms of “celebration” will be more or less warranted, depending on the seriousness of the transgression and the nature of the relationship between artist and alleged “victim.”  Are we talking a series of rape allegations by credible accusers or one isolated incident involving an off-color joke?  The nature of the moral transgression matters for our judgment about how much, if any, “celebration” of an artist’s work is morally defensible, as does the credibility or character of the persons in question.  These kinds of contextual details can range from morally significant to morally irrelevant for our examination of the tension between the merits of a piece of art and the reputation of its creator.

(A brief side note: some commenters on this issue like to pretend that artworks can be appreciated in a kind of pure aesthetic vacuum, where all details about the artwork’s creative context are completely irrelevant to the process of appreciation.  I have trouble imagining such a space, and I doubt that in the real world anyone is truly capable of divorcing artwork from the biography of the artist(s) who made it or the cultural context to which it refers.  This seems like an untenable position to defend since it contradicts everything we know about conscious perception or meaning making.  If you aim to defend such an “art-stands-on-its-own” ideal, your team should be prepared to grapple with (non-straw person) counter-arguments that emphasize the inevitable overlap of our interpretations of art with moral and cultural norms—not to mention the scientific evidence on conscious associations and moral cognition.)

It might help to use a few contrasting examples of how producers or curators handled the “celebration” of artworks made by morally compromised artists to illustrate why a “one-size-fits-all” approach is insufficient.  Which (if either) museum handled the Chuck Close controversy better and why—The National Gallery of Art in Washington or the Pennsylvania Academy of the Fine Arts?  Did Netflix do the right thing by firing Kevin Spacey but continuing to make available the previous five seasons of House of Cards?  In what sense is Netflix’s compromise a “celebration” of Spacey’s acting performance (not to mention the contributions of other actors and production staff)?  Did Spotify make the right call to remove Bill Cosby and Louis C.K. from their Top-Ranked Comedy playlists?(a)  You should illustrate your team’s position on Q-1 using such examples to draw important distinctions about the context or content of these artists’ work, as well as their moral transgressions and the resulting negative effects.  We draw moral lines in the sand to protect vulnerable parties, as well as for other reasons that the judges (and the other team) should hear about.  You need not be exhaustive with your supporting examples, but having some on hand that help illustrate your argument will significantly strengthen your position on this case.  (And for some people, their judgments about censoring art to any degree will depend on the morally significant details of these examples.  Choose wisely which examples best support your argument.)

A further factor to consider in defining what form a “celebration” might take is the degree of certainty the producers or curators of the artwork have about the alleged guilt of the artist.  Keep at the forefront of your minds that the case description asks “…whether the work of […] artists accused of questionable conduct needs to be revisited or recontextualized [by those who curate the art]…even before a courtroom determined guilt” (my emphasis).  The case cites various examples of alleged transgressors, each of which may have unique complications surrounding the allegations or varying trajectories in the courts’ attempts to establish the truth of the allegations.  Moreover, for some examples noted (e.g., Piccasso, Louis C. K.) the individuals were never brought to trial, even though a range of negative consequences may have ensued (from severe to none). It would be wrong to overgeneralize too much about all such cases involving famous artists or producers accused or convicted of sexual misconduct.  What these examples have in common is their shared status as famous artists whose work is either in the process of being “celebrated” in some form, being re-evaluated as a candidate for future “celebration,” or retrospectively being reconsidered as worthy of admiration and respect.  Since “those who curate the art” are not judges or juries bound by formal rules of due process, nor are they privy to all of the relevant information that criminal courts might possess, their judgments should exhibit appropriate caution.

Ethics Bowl teams should consider how much certainty that producers, curators or the general public actually possess about the alleged transgressions of the artist in question, as available facts could vary widely.  We know, too, that some accusations or conclusions made in the court of public opinion were later found to be unjustified.(b)  As philosopher Ben Burgis points out regarding the example of sexual misconduct allegations made against filmmaker Woody Allen, the public’s access to the truth about the alleged misconduct that took place in private 30 years ago is limited (especially given that accounts by Allen and Mia Farrow’s adult children conflict significantly).(c)  This puts our certainty about Allen’s guilt on more shaky footing than in cases where full confessions of guilt are available. 

We also know that American police departments and legal institutions charged with investigating such cases have a mixed record, especially where sexual misconduct allegations come from women or minorities and involve figures in positions of power.(d)  Furthermore, as the #MeToo movement has repeatedly emphasized, many sectors of the entertainment industry or art world have a very poor record of taking seriously the sexual misconduct allegations brought forward women actors, models, musicians or other artists, since the fields in which these artists work have been disproportionately controlled by men (who often are shielded by a patriarchal culture of male dominance still prevalent in their fields).  Similar concerns have been raised on behalf of allegations brought forward by LGBTQ artists.(e)

Do these complications mean we can never have any degree of certainty?  No.  But there are a few starter questions to consider and guideposts to help you navigate the ethical swamp here.  Should your team emphasize a strict innocent until proven guilty principle, and trust fully the investigative institutions or governing bodies to properly police and report such transgressions?  Or should you take a more skeptical accounting of the available data on sexual misconduct allegations?  Surely, it’s not the case that we know nothing about these records of sexual misconduct (i.e., total skepticism isn’t warranted).  Equally likely is that some accounts or studies of these patterns of misconduct by famous artists are better than others (so you’ll need to cite available data from reputable sources).  Our degree of certainty about allegations made against a given artist should track the quality of evidence supporting the victim’s claims, as well as the historical record of allegations within that institution or field of employment.  When certainty is compromised, the strength of our convictions about the alleged guilt of the artist should be dialed down. (1)   

Given all of these complications affecting our degree of certainty about the reporting or the investigation of sexual misconduct allegations, it might be wise to align your team’s position to reflect: a) any evidence of bias in a given case; b) what we know about the power dynamics involved in the artistic institutions in question; as well as c) the rights of all parties to due process and fair consideration of their grievances.  Stronger positions will account for these bias concerns and varied records of institutional accountability.  Ethics Bowl judges are also likely to favor positions on this case that are backed by reliable evidence, interpreted fairly and accurately, as well as those that are sensitive to the unique context of each example noted in the case description (or cited beyond the case description).

Question 2 (Q-2) asks you to consider, if a given body of artwork is “historically transformative and has produced an immeasurable amount of good for humanity,” then Does celebration of the art excuse the (possibly unrelated) transgression(s) of the artist?  Again, if this is the moderator’s question for you, from the outset establish clear definitions of key words like “celebration,” “excuse,” and “unrelated” to make your team’s position coherent and well-grounded in shared assumptions.

The crux of this question, I think, can be restated as: Is it even possible to “celebrate” (award esteem and recognition to) an important body of artwork without sanctioning or minimizing the morally problematic actions of its creator?  Depending on which definition of excuse one emphasizes, the implications of this question for the integrity of the art world and the moral climate of a society will be far-reaching: 1a: to make apology for, b: to try to remove blame from; 2: to forgive entirely or disregard as of trivial import : regard as excusable; 3a: to grant exemption or release to, b: to allow to leave; 4: to serve as excuse for : JUSTIFY. (i)  One helpful exercise is to substitute for “excuse” in Q-2 each of these senses of the term in order to test your moral intuitions for each independently. 

I don’t know about you, but, no matter which definition I substitute, if I were the victim of abuse perpetrated by such a monumentally important artist, the ongoing “celebration” of this artist’s work would feel like the harm I suffered was being minimized (or ignored altogether).  Even more so if the artist’s creations were somehow offered up as some kind of moral compensation for the transgressive behavior in question.  While it may not be sufficient to adopt such a personal point of view to address this question, it may be necessary to do so in order to grasp what it’s like to be a sexual abuse victim forever associated with the work of a famous artist.  The best positions on Ethics Bowl cases will strive for clarity and objectivity without losing appreciation for what a personal perspective can reveal, morally speaking.  What’s at stake for victims here is fundamentally personal in nature—i.e., their self-worth, dignity and ongoing agency—which requires what philosophers call intersubjectivity in order to apprehend.  (You can’t have the same private experience as someone else, but our moral imaginations give us some access to others’ private experience because we, ourselves, have had similar or relatable experiences with which we come to grasp why the self-worth, dignity and ongoing agency of persons matter.)  It should go without saying that this is equally true for artists who are falsely accused but whose reputation could be forever suspect once sexual misconduct allegations go public.  Carefully appreciating the deeply personal consequences of these sexual misconduct cases will allow you to grapple with whatever sense of excuse is conveyed in Q-2.

There’s another tricky element involved in Q-2 (which is perhaps included by the case authors to test how closely you’re considering what is morally relevant in cases like this).  The first sentence of Q-2 introduces the supposition of a work of art that “…is historically transformative and has produced an immeasurable amount of good for humanity—akin to a revolutionary advancement in technology or medicine.”  To assess how much this matters, consider that the personal devastation alluded to in the paragraph above would be just as relevant for a sexual misconduct case involving a relatively unknown artist, no?  Just as a court of law might determine that some evidence is irrelevant to the matter of establishing the defendant’s guilt, to fixate on the relation between the cultural impact of an artist’s creations and the determination of his or her alleged guilt would introduce a red herring.  A celebrated artist who commits rape is still a rapist, and their fame is irrelevant to society’s assessment of their character or their crime.  We can probably safely assume that their status as “celebrated” artists conveys some sense of worth projected onto their artwork (which is a safe assumption for the artists cited in the case description—i.e., they all were/are extremely talented, perhaps even “masters of their craft”). 

But maybe some artist’s work is so stellar in quality that we could make a case that the artwork “excuses” transgressions of respect and decency, even violations of human rights.  Perhaps, following a kind of utilitarian logic, you can imagine a “celebrated” novelist who has written a hugely-influential book about—among other things—sexual misconduct, which sells millions of copies and influences countless people to take these transgressions more seriously, as well as victim’s rights and testimonies more seriously.  Imagine too that with all the public good that comes from this novel, it comes to light that the author is alleged to have “done research” by sexually harassing and abusing vulnerable people.  Ramp up the stakes even more in your thought experiment: make her victims minors and the abuse allegations even more horrible.  Whatever the circumstances, will there ever be a morally defensible calculation of maximized utility produced by the novel’s greatness that “excuses” such crimes?  I’ll leave that for your team to ponder. 

As noted earlier, “those who curate the art” are not judges or juries bound by courtroom procedures or a legal code of ethics.  But in their capacity as the gatekeepers of the art world, many will argue that curators have a moral responsibility to respond to allegations—past or present—involving an artist they showcase in a manner that reflects the integrity of the institutions they represent, as well as the shared moral codes we collectively rely on to live with ourselves.  (Few would argue that a curator must completely separate their own moral conscience entirely from their work.)  This doesn’t mean that curators must themselves be moral role models, nor does it mean that their institution (museum, production company, media platform) must present itself as a guardian of public morals.  But as gatekeepers with some degree of power and as members of a wider moral community, the quality of their response to the allegations will send a message about the seriousness of sexual misconduct anywhere in society.  It will also send a message about their own institutional reputation (and perhaps even their personal character).  Being indifferent to the scandal would also send a message, so that’s probably not an option for curators either.  In short, a lot of real-world evidence suggests that the art world is never completely separate from the messy business of ethics, and that there is more at stake in these decisions than the institution’s stock value or financial endowment (although those may also be affected by a bungling of a sexual misconduct scandal). 

The takeaway question here: Is it morally relevant how famous or great the art or artist is when determining whether a body of art could ever “excuse” a moral transgression like [most cases of] sexual misconduct?  Again, wouldn’t the seriousness of the moral choice here be the same if the artist in question were relatively unknown? (A final note on this point: as noted earlier with Q-1, maybe what is morally relevant for this question is the credibility or seriousness of the allegation—as opposed to how great the art might be.  Maybe your team is ready to conclude that a body of immensely  influential and beneficial artwork is enough to “excuse”—overlook? counter-balance? make amends for?—one isolated minor accusation of sexual misconduct, thereby warranting no “art with asterisks” in a museum.  On the other hand, maybe for most sexual misconduct cases—like those noted in the case description—your team may decide to prioritize the seriousness of the allegations over the work’s cultural or artistic significance, concluding that no great art can ever “excuse” moral transgressions of this kind.)

A related red herring that could stem from a careless reading of Q-2 would be to confuse an artist’s personal artistic mission vis-à-vis morality with the role of a curator’s moral responsibilities in showcasing the resulting art.  Unlike last year’s Regional Case #14 “American Dirt,” Q-2 is not asking you if artists themselves should make art that is receptive to reasonable moral considerations; it is asking you to reflect on the moral responsibilities of curators who are in a position to “celebrate” in some form the work of an allegedly morally-compromised artist.  There may be great art out there that is amoral in nature or arguably immoral in some respects, and is still worth curating or even “celebrating” in some capacity.  The morality of the art produced in this case is a separate issue (as are discussions about the relation between the two).  What is at issue here is what curators of art ought to consider when they decide—if they decide—to showcase a “celebrated” artist’s work whose moral character and conduct is, to varying degrees, implicated by a sexual misconduct scandal.  In other words, don’t get sidetracked in your team’s position by the question of how much—if at all—morality should factor in the creation of art. This case is about the moral responsibilities of those curating art.

Q-3 of the case is What does it mean to display art “with an asterisk?” How much consideration should curators give to the psychological safety of art consumers?  Since my case analysis is already fairly long, I’m going to leave this one to your team, trusting that you can apply the relevant considerations I raised above to prepare for this question.

Good luck in your preparations and on “Bowl Day”!

Footnotes:

(1) Given past discrimination against women and LGBTQ persons and—historically at least—the patriarchal bent of our artistic institutions, my own bias on this issue of reliability of sexual misconduct claims and investigations leads me to first give the benefit of doubt to reporters of abuse, as there is an established precedent in many entertainment fields of women and LGBTQ voices being unjustly discounted.(f)  However, all of us are human and therefore susceptible to the same kinds of cognitive biases.(g)  We’re learning more each year about the prevalence and reporting of sexual violence against women and gender minorities, and research on these trends shows that a variety of complicating factors are at play.(h)

Endnotes:

(a) Resnikoff, Paul. “Spotify Removes Bill Cosby and Louis C.K. from Top-Ranked Comedy Playlists.” Digital Music News, May 11, 2018. https://www.digitalmusicnews.com/2018/05/11/spotify-bill-cosby-louis-c-k/.

(b) Artland Editors. “10 Controversial Artworks That Changed Art History.” Artland. Retrieved: 10-7-21.. https://magazine.artland.com/10-controversial-artworks-changed-art-history/.

(c) Burgis, Ben. “Separating the Art from the Artist: Woody Allen, Marilyn Manson, and George W. Bush.” Zero Books on YouTube, March 2, 2021, https://youtu.be/mk-iQ3Ca04s.

(d) Frye, Jocelyn, et al. “Transforming the Culture of Power: An Examination of Gender-Based Violence in the United States.” Center for American Progress. October 31, 2019. https://www.americanprogress.org/issues/women/reports/2019/10/31/476588/transforming-culture-power/.

(e) [Example case] Gelt, Jessica. “The sexual misconduct allegations rocking L.A.’s largest LGBTQ theater company.” L.A. Times, May 28, 2021. Retrieved 11-15-21. https://www.latimes.com/entertainment-arts/story/2021-05-28/celebration-gay-theater-michael-shepperd-sexual-misconduct-allegations

(f) Jones, Trina, and Emma E. Wade. “Me too: Race, gender, and ending workplace sexual harassment.” Duke J. Gender L. & Pol’y 27 (2020): 203. https://scholarship.law.duke.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?referer=&httpsredir=1&article=1353&context=djglp.

(g) Monahan, J., and S. Polk. “The effect of cultural bias on the investigation and prosecution of sexual assault.” Police Chief Magazine (2018). https://www.policechiefmagazine.org/the-effect-of-cultural-bias-on-the-investigation/  b) Latack, Jessica A., et al. “Attentional bias for sexual threat among sexual victimization survivors: A meta-analytic review.” Trauma, violence, & abuse 18.2 (2017): 172-184. https://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pmc/articles/PMC5593786/

(h) Tjaden, Patricia Godeke, and Nancy Thoennes. “Full report of the prevalence, incidence, and consequences of violence against women.” (2000). https://www.ojp.gov/pdffiles1/nij/183781.pdf.

(i) Miriam-Webster Definition of excuse (transitive verb). https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/excuse

NHSEB 2021-2022 Regionals Cases Initial Thoughts—Full Set

1: The Social (Experiment) Network – Facebook could direct its algorithms to encourage outbreaks of collaboration, civility and purposefulness. Instead, it distracts users with triviality, spreads misinformation and sows anger, all in the service of maximizing ad revenue. Running comparatively innocuous experiments (of course attitudes are contagious… was an experiment really needed?) is low on the platform’s list of sins. More appropriate targets for analysis could be a) whether a wise person should allow themselves to be distracted and manipulated by social media at all, b) whether Facebook usage, like other habit-forming vices, should be limited to users over 18 or 21, or c) whether Facebook should accept lower ad revenues in exchange for using its power to uplift rather than devolve humanity.

2: Trust the Science – Since we rely on the media to make important healthcare decisions (Should I wear a mask? Which mask? Where? Should I get a shot? Which shot? When?), outlets have an obligation to present information in a nuanced, contextualized fashion. However, as the case notes, “even the most reputable media still rely on gaining consumers through attention-grabbing headlines and engaging content,” meaning that outlets have a financial incentive to sensationalize, which too often leaves us scared, divided and confused as to whom to trust. With the power to inspire vaccine enthusiasm or hesitance, virus precautions or disregard, responsibility falls on news producers to present information in a way that empowers sober, fact-based, compassionate decision-making.

3: Boy, Bye: Or, On the Ethics of Ghosting – It would be kind for Imani to send her online connections a brief goodbye. But given that their relationships are new, superficial and 100% digital, she has no strong obligation to do so. Risk of being “ghosted” is taken for granted in the online dating culture, especially in the early stages. And so none of her aspiring love interests would likely be hurt too terribly if she simply disappeared.

4: Suffering in the Wild – Our obligation to ease the suffering of wild animals is strongest for species and populations most impacted by human activity (through habitat destruction, ecosystem disruption, poaching), and our permission to intervene in the natural order strongest to the extent changes are reversible, modest and planned. Gene editing without careful consideration of the long-term impacts would be reckless, whereas relocating animals to a more accommodating habitat could be fine. Vaccinations would be somewhere in between, and the elimination of all carnivores, through extinction or gene modification, is an interesting possibility deserving additional reflection. (If we could modify the natural order such that mice, deer and salmon died of old age rather than owl, coyote or grizzly attack, and if we could avoid or curb overpopulation, wouldn’t that be a happier world? Maybe keep carnivores that eat mice…)

5: Predictive Policing – So long as proactive crime-prevention is positive (helping the unemployed find work, the homeless find shelter, the addicted receive rehabilitation assistance) and genuinely encouraging (as opposed to demeaning or belittling), it sounds like a win-win, similar to programs that proactively reach out to patients statistically at risk of suicide. Citizens contacted by “life support officers” in a coach-like fashion (if that’s indeed their approach), should welcome the support, and the state’s interest in their success could turn around an otherwise unhappy and destructive life trajectory.

6: AppleScare – Apple’s strategy of converting known problematic images into numbers, then scanning phones for those numbers (rather than downloading, viewing or otherwise accessing users’ personal images) is a reasonable compromise between respecting user privacy and deterring child abuse. A similar strategy might be devised for anti-terrorism and other legitimate purposes.

7: 23 & Memaw – (After a little reflection, I flipped my stance on this one, so be sure to give it time to marinate.) Since everyone seems to have hated Nancy’s grandfather (who turns out wasn’t her mother’s biological father after all), Nancy should tell her mother what she discovered through genetic testing, assuming she has good reason to think it will do more to fill her mother with joy as opposed to resentment or anger. Whatever the case, the impact on her mother should be the primary driver of Nancy’s decision – given that the man died before she was born, and the fact that her mother is in poor health, Nancy’s personal curiosity shouldn’t weigh as heavily.

8: Art with an Asterisk— Imagine that [insert the worst villain you can imagine] were secretly a master sculptor, and their work discovered after their death. Surely we could marvel at the magnificence of and skill behind the art while still denouncing the person’s behavior. However, we should be sensitive to living victims, ensure that our appreciation of the art isn’t confused with appreciation for the person, and that its display doesn’t enrich the artist unless they’ve repented, been reformed and forgiven. Bottom line: art stands on its own.

9: Priorities, Priorities – Analogous scenario: two patients are in need of a liver transplant, the first due to alcoholism, the second due to a congenital condition. Since the first drank excessively knowing that this could harm their liver, if there’s only one liver to allocate, all else equal, the patient in need through no fault of their own should be prioritized (though if there’s an abundance of livers, everyone gets one). Similarly, absent mitigating circumstances and all else equal, COVID-19 patients who chose to not take reasonable precautions to prevent severe illness (who go unvaccinated, who gather with large groups indoors for frivolous reasons such as entertainment, who choose not to properly wear an effective mask) should be de-prioritized for ICU beds (though if there’s an abundance of beds, everyone gets one). Mitigating circumstances might include the patient’s age (and amount of life left to live), chances of recovery (would ICU care even help?), and responsibilities (a mother of five young children, a surgeon with rare, in-demand skills, an ethics bowl blogger – kidding!). However, to the extent a patient’s behavior was reasonable in light of their education and access to information (imagine a person lacking basic investigative skills, surrounded by anti-vax family and friends, and awash in anti-vax propaganda), they are less to blame because based on their info, inferences and social pressures, going unvaccinated and maskless may have been the reasonable, healthy choice, and therefore their prioritization would be partially redeemed. (Note the connection between this case and case 2: Trust the Science.)

10: Are You My Mother? – All else equal, while genetic parents should receive custody (or partial custody as in the second case), the birth mother (essentially the surrogate mother, lacking genetic connection) deserves substantial compensation from the clinic that caused the error, not only to amend for the heartbreak of losing a child with whom she’s no doubt bonded, but also for the extreme burden of gestating (changing the woman emotionally and physically forever), and to give all fertility clinics strong financial incentive to prevent similar errors.

11: Just The Facts – Avoiding the appearance of biased reporting is essential to serious news outlets’ credibility. Of course, some outlets don’t care – Fox intentionally positions itself as pro-conservative, MSNBC as pro-liberal, RT as a pro-Russia. But for sources claiming disinterested presentation of objective facts, there’s nothing wrong with reassigning reporters when their background or history suggests a possible bias. Analogous situation: helping organize the Los Angeles HSEB, I once had a judge rush into the hallway to tell me she knew a member of a team whom had just sat down. Solution: I swapped that judge with a judge in another room – not because the first was incapable of judging the teams fairly, but to avoid even the appearance of favoritism, to proactively defend the legitimacy of the outcome. News outlets desiring similar credibility with their readers/listeners/viewers may swap reporters for similar reasons.

12: Paralympic Pay Parity – Paralympic competitors are usually missing a limb due to circumstances beyond their control (congenital, accidental), and so since they didn’t do anything to deserve their physical state, paying them less is in some sense unfair. However, public interest in the Olympics (indicated by viewership and merchandise sales) and the higher revenue the heightened interest generates suggest a higher perceived value and make more funds available for distribution. Therefore, since the public seems to care more about and spend more on the Olympics, paying Olympians more is legit.

13: Fake Views – As deepfake tech becomes more pervasive, the global “truth crisis” will accelerate and expand, undermining trust and certainty, and destabilizing societies. To offset this impact, producers should include disclaimers when deepfake tech is used for acceptable reasons (for example, to dramatically portray a true event), and news sources should vet and only release received footage once confirmed genuine and/or include warning labels such as, “Possible Deepfake – event not yet confirmed.”

14: Familial Obligations – Amir should simply disclose his situation. Any satisfaction his mother might enjoy by believing he is financially successful is being overridden by her and the rest of his Lebanese family’s disappointment, jealousy and spite, caused by their false impression that he’s wealthy and has forgotten about them. Assuming they’ve been good to him, he does have an obligation to help his sister and mother. Why? If it weren’t for their support and love, he wouldn’t be the person he is, and therefore should repay them with care and support in turn, at least as he’s able (though his primary obligations would indeed be to his dependent child with the pressing, expensive medical need, due to the child’s vulnerability and the fact that Amir helped bring the child into existence).

15: All Eyes on You – Physical surveillance on school grounds is one thing, but students’ private lives should be shielded from intrusion. It’s belittling and demeaning enough to be monitored and overseen during the school day, treated in many cases more like an inmate to be controlled than a person to be nurtured. Giving students space to be themselves after school (and in some cases to make a few mistakes) is part of growing up, preparing them to become responsible members of free society. Schools should therefore minimize monitoring of all non-official and after-hours student activity, and clearly disclose which communications and activities are being surveilled.

Expanded Case Analysis Example: K-Pop

EthicsBowl.org contributor, ethics bowl coach and judge, Michael Andersen, recently shared several examples of expanded case analysis worksheets he creates for his team (a lucky team indeed!). The format: generate interest with engaging media, share the case as originally presented, consider tweaked discussion questions, offer bonus research resources, and close out by connecting the current case to related cases. I think it’s a marvelous approach, and thank Michael for his permission to share an example with our readers. If you have your own coaching tips or resource samples to share with the community, we’d be happy to feature them. Just reach out to matt (at) mattdeaton.com, or use the contact form at MattDeaton.com. Thanks as always, Michael!

Ethics Club 11/5/20 EB Case #7. The Korean Pop Industrial Complex

Today’s Discussion Topic: Do listeners have a moral obligation to stop supporting the K-Pop industry if they know that performers are mistreated? Is the entertainment industry inherently exploitative?

Pre-Discussion Resources:

2020-21 Regional Ethics Bowl Case #7. The Korean Pop Industrial Complex

Within the past decade, Korean Pop, more commonly known as K-Pop, has rapidly become a global sensation. South Korean artists have hit the Billboard Hot 100 chart at least eight times. In 2019, BTS became the first K-Pop group to be nominated for a Grammy. Adored due to its distinctive blend of catchy tunes, clean choreography, and glamorous idols, the K-Pop industry has grown along with the rise of Hallyu, a Chinese term which describes the popularity of South Korean culture internationally.1 Via Korean pop, drama, skincare regimens, and more, South Korea has become a fixture in popular culture worldwide.2

In an increasingly globalized society, many think that the rise of K-Pop is a force of moral good. Cultural globalization allows people from all parts of the world to understand one another and appreciate different ideas, meanings, and values. In turn, this enables the ability to empathize and relate to others, no matter where they are from. K-Pop is also a way for South Korea to develop its “soft power”, which describes the “intangible power a country wields through its image, rather than through hard force,” such as military or economic power.3

However, for K-Pop performers, the journey to fame is a grueling one. Stories of tired performers putting up a happy front to excitedly greet fans is not uncommon in an industry where exploitative contracts, demanding beauty ideals, and even human rights violations are mainstay. K-Pop performers work long hours which go largely undercompensated, as the money their content earns is often funneled back into corporate hands or toward chipping away at looming debt.4 Plastic surgery, too, is an open secret in the industry.5 Many trainees are expected to go under the knife, with the most common procedures designed to achieve highly-coveted features like double eyelids or a straighter nose. Of additional concern, sexual exploitation is a quiet phenomenon and a common truth for women in Korean entertainment. Young performers are often taken advantage of by power brokers behind closed doors. In a culture which often stigmatizes sexuality, these scandals are obscured from public view.6 Moreover, the K-Pop industry exists to meet and cater to the demands of a hungry fanbase, who are consistently starved for new content. Fans are often criticized for propagating a system which treats its artists poorly.

Still, many assert that K-Pop is a net good. Although the exploitative habits of the industry are suspect, performers voluntarily enter their contracts. Additionally, Korean culture emphasizes work ethic. According to the OECD, “South Koreans work more hours per week on average than all but one other country, and almost 50% more than famously industrious Germany.”7 To criticize the K-Pop industry based on the dedication of performers, some argue, would be inconsiderate of differing cultural values..

DISCUSSION QUESTIONS: ​(Slightly modified and extended from ​original Qs​)​:

  1. Do listeners have a moral obligation to stop supporting the K-Pop industry if they know that performers are mistreated?
  2. a) If people voluntarily enter contracts, does it matter that the terms of the contract are exploitative or otherwise unethical? b) How can we distinguish between coercion and voluntary agreement?
  3. a) Is the entertainment industry inherently exploitative? b) How should we decide if working conditions should be properly described as “exploitative” and therefore morally impermissible?

Helpful (But Optional) Resources for Further Study:

  1. (Video) “The Late Capitalism of K-Pop​” @ Jonas Čeika – CCK Philosophy.​[17:33] While I was not able to find any biographical details of this video essayist with an admittedly leftist bent, his analysis of the K-Pop industrial complex in Korea presents some helpful historical and philosophical context. In this notes for the video, he cites his sources as well as corrections to the script since the publication of the video in 2017–a signifier of some intellectual credibility, at least.
  2. (Video) “Does Capitalism Exploit Workers?​” @ Libertarianism.org. [6:07] ​For a contrary view to the video above (although not focused on the K-Pop context), U. San Diego Philosophy Prof. Matt Zwolinski explains why capitalism actually tends to protect workers’ interests. “The idea that capitalism exploits workers stems from Karl Marx’s work in the late 1800s. Although the definition of “exploitation” has changed since then, many still believe capitalist systems take advantage of vulnerable workers. …Zwolinski contends that even if it were exploitative, increasing political regulation and control would actually make the problem worse. Increases in government make citizens more vulnerable to the state.”
  3. (Article) “Exploitation | The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy​” ​“​To exploit someone is​to take unfair advantage of them. It is to use another person’s vulnerability for one’s own benefit. Of course, benefiting from another’s vulnerability is not always morally wrong—we do not condemn a chess player for exploiting a weakness in his opponent’s defense, for instance. But some forms of advantage-taking do seem to be clearly wrong, and it is this normative sense of exploitation that is of primary interest to moral and political philosophers….”
  4. (Video) “What is Consent?: Consent #1 – Ethics | WIRELESS PHILOSOPHY​” ​[6:50] What is consent? In this Wireless Philosophy video, Prof. Tom Dougherty (University of Cambridge) considers the nature of consent and its relationship to morality, rights, and harm.
  5. (Video) “Consent and Rights: Consent #2 – Ethics | WIRELESS PHILOSOPHY​” ​[7:53] In this Wireless Philosophy video, Prof. Tom Dougherty (University of Cambridge) continues his exploration of the nature of consent and its relationship to morality, rights, and harm.
  6. (Article) “Exploding the myths behind K-pop | Bright and irresistible, K-pop provides the beat to South Korea’s youth culture. But behind the perfect smiles and dance routines are tales of sexism and abuse​.” By Crystal Tai, The Guardian​, Sun 29 Mar 2020.
  7. (Article) “A**holes, job dependency, and intimacy: 3 reasons it’s hard to end harassment in Hollywood | The way the film and TV industries are structured makes them a breeding ground for abuse​.” By Emily VanDerWerff, ​Vox​, Nov 17, 2017.
  8. (Article) “Sexual Abuse in the Entertainment Industry.​” @ NWG Network, Oct 23, 2017.

Related Ethics Bowl Cases:

  1. (Related Ethics Bowl Case) 2014-15 National EB Case #2: Ethical Consumerism​“Maria wonders whether it is morally acceptable to buy cheap products manufactured by people working for low wages in bad conditions. Are we morally obligated to ensure that none of our actions indirectly harm others?”
  2. (Related Ethics Bowl Case) 2015-16 National Case #2: Prison Work​​“Many states make use of work prisons where prisoners “volunteer” to work and then receive a wage. Does this constitute exploitation of prisoners or is it necessary to reduce the high cost of the criminal justice system and help prisoners gain work skills? Is it ethical for a private company to pay workers in prison less than workers outside prison? Is it ethical for private companies to earn a profit from prison labor?”
  3. (Related Ethics Bowl Case) 2014-2015 National Case #6. NFL Fandom​“Is being a fan of the NFL football morally defensible? Critics state the NFL treats players as faceless commodities, and football is a potentially dangerous and degrading activity. Supporters stress the importance of players’ consent.”

(De)funding the Police – NHSEB 2020-2021 National Case 13

As case 13 explains, not all people who use the divisive catchphrase, “defund the police” actually want to abolish police departments. Some do. But many simply want to divert some funds to education, employment, social work and mental health resources. Why? Studies have shown that educational and employment equity better decreases crime. A better educated populace would intuitively be happier, more successful and therefore more law-abiding. And while cutting police budgets might give departments good reason to behave, it might also be a good idea to keep a few cops around.

However, case 13 doesn’t say much about reforming policing techniques and attitudes, which opens an opportunity for ethics bowlers to add something to the discussion. Many police forces take an overly militaristic approach to their work inappropriate for civilian policing, one that can unnecessarily escalate encounters and perpetuate a contentious culture.

Or so argues former police officer turned University of South Carolina law professor Seth Stoughton. Below is Stoughton’s TED talk on just that subject, followed by my own take on his argument. I’ll be discussing it with my ethics bowl team this weekend, and also sharing the TED vid from 0:15 – 2:17 and 10:00 – 12:30. Enjoy!

Dining Out During a Pandemic – NHSEB 2020-2021 National Case 6

This year 2020 faced a global crisis through the Pandemic COVID-19, formerly known as SARS-CoV-2. In early March of this year, many stores in the United States began closing down, and the economy began to shut down. Organizations deemed as non-essential were closed, and the people were instructed to remain in their homes unless they absolutely needed to go out. This case study analysis will address some ethical issues regarding dining out during the pandemic.

This guest post was graciously written by Mr. Luis Villanueva of East Texas.

Is it unethical to dine-in at restaurants in the midst of a pandemic such as COVID-19? The answer to this question is yes, it can be. However, it can also be unethical not to allow restaurants to remain in business.

It can be unethical to dine out during the pandemic because doing so unnecessarily increases the likelihood of the disease spreading out. Eating out requires taking off protective masks which the CDC (Centers For Disease Control and Prevention) deems necessary to protect the public. Taking off the mask at one’s table and calling it the “off mask” section is like being in a pool and calling a certain area the “pee section.” It’s going to spread! The urine will travel through the water just like the virus would travel through the air. Moreover, there is really no way to completely eliminate the chances of catching the virus while dining out. Because people eat out at public restaurants, they are putting themselves and others at risk of infection, and it is therefore not the best ethical decision.

It can also be unethical to close down a family restaurant. Refraining from supporting a dear one’s business would de-emphasize the needs and interests of loved ones. Say for instance there is a single-mother working hard to feed her seven young daughters, and she owns a restaurant that provides her only source of income. Shutting it down would place her in a very difficult dilemma. Does she close and let her daughters starve? Or does she keep her business open at the cost of increasing the risk of viral infection?

What about the immediate people who work for her, like cooks and waiters? Closing down the restaurant would also cost these people their jobs and their ability to take care of their families.  Statistically speaking, they have a much greater chance of surviving the COVID-19 virus than they do surviving starvation from lack of food or shelter. Keeping the restaurant open is not meant to be an easy ethical choice. And certainly this pandemic year has not necessarily been the most enjoyable, fun, or thrilling year for everyone (although some folks have been able to find so many things to be grateful for even in a year like 2020). From a Care Ethics perspective, it would be understandable, and ethical, if the single-mother kept her restaurant open to prioritize the basic needs of her seven little girls. 

What responsibility do Andy and Megan have to protect the health of others, especially if those others choose to put themselves at risk? As the article explains, Megan and Andy used to go out to eat quite a lot before the pandemic. This of course strengthened the profits of the businesses where they dined. Some could say though that they both have a responsibility to stay at home to decrease the chance of spreading the disease. Even if others choose to put themselves at risk by going to public restaurants, Megan and Andy could avoid dining out in order to protect people from greater risk of infection. Not going out to restaurants could be Megan and Andy’s contribution to reduce the chances of spreading COVID-19.

How should decisions balancing the support of the economy and the protection of people’s health be made during a pandemic?  This question is really where everything is headed to. What is the balance? Perhaps one could use the production-possibilities frontier to explain what the best course of action would be. This process is very similar to a consequentialist perspective that strives to maximize profit or “net pleasure.” So, according to the production-possibilities frontier, there exists the right amount to balance out supporting the economy and protecting people’s health.

Say for example, that the country closes down all stores altogether, including gas stations, supermarkets, and of course all restaurants. This would be inefficient because people would likely perish from hunger and thirst even so more than they would from the coronavirus. On the other hand, if all restaurants remained open as they normally are, and, just to make things interesting, if all senior citizens who are vulnerable to the virus were given free groceries or meals as an incentive to get out of the house more, then virus cases would skyrocket considerably and possibly turn out fatal for the people of tertiary age. So what the PPF (production-possibilities frontier) would suggest is to do what maximizes net safety. That is, keep enough supermarkets and shops so that people don’t starve out of their basic needs, while at the same time close many others down so as to negate the effect of rising coronavirus cases.

The Korean Pop Industrial Complex – NHSEB 2020-2021 National Case 7

Matt could identify the “I Got It From My Daddy” guy in sunglasses, but that’s it. Which is why Arsheen was a much better fit for this case. Thanks for guest authoring, Arsheen! Image credit to PostKulture.

It’s no secret that K-pop idols are overworked. They’re pressured to constantly improve their talent and image, and to create a never-ending flow of new music and dances. As a K-pop fan of 4 years, I believe listeners have a moral obligation to stop supporting the current industry trajectory and demand a more ethical working environment.

Many fans already do this without even thinking. Min Yoongi, better known as Suga, is the main rapper in the world-famous K-pop group BTS. He recently had his shoulder labrum torn and had to undergo surgery. His fans know that he is in pain and needs time to heal. Therefore, most have been patient and caring for his health and recovery. Fans know that Min Yoongi’s injury may affect BTS’s new album release planned for November 20, but they are ok with it. This is just one example of fans wanting better for their idols.

Many fans have tried to get their voices heard about idols being overworked. Another example is Park Jimin, more commonly known as Jimin from BTS. About three years ago, Park Jimin was overworking himself so much that he needed medical attention. He was not eating enough and was working too much. Many fans were upset with BigHIt, BTS’s label, as they did not do anything to help. Instead, they pushed him to almost work himself to death. 

The K-pop industry is very competitive. Many, if not all of the idols, start their training at 13 or 14. The teenage years are when individuals don’t make the best decisions. Because of this fact, I believe it does matter if the terms of the contract are exploitative, taking unfair advantage of youth hungry for fame. 

I believe that the entertainment industry is inherently exploitative. For example, many K-pop industries do not allow their idols to date. This is because “taken” idols can lower the industry’s revenue compared idols who are single. Dating can lower revenue because every fan has that longing feeling that the idol may end up dating them. If they find out that their idol is already dating someone, they may lose interest.

Another reason why the entertainment industry is inherently exploitative is that idols are forced to undergo plastic surgery to make themselves look perfect. Those who don’t simply can’t compete. And the extreme pressure K-pop stars are under, combined their usually young age, makes any choice they make less than ideally voluntary.

For these reasons, I believe the K-pop industry needs substantial reform. Rising stars will have little power to fight back. And since the culture is driven by money, changes will likely have to be demanded by fans. Therefore, the greatest responsibility to reform the K-pop industry falls on existing stars and K-pop fans like myself. We can still enjoy the music. But we should use our purchasing power to reward labels who decrease these harms, and punish labels who perpetuate them.

Factory Farming – NHSEB 2020-2021 National Case 1

Case 1 this NHSEB season comes out pretty hard against factory farming. This is uncharacteristic of ethics bowl cases, which usually offer a decent balance of reasons for and against. The lopsided presentation may be appropriate due to just how difficult factory farming is to morally defend. However, one angle to consider is how beef production and consumption doesn’t seem quite as morally problematic as other forms of meat.

Napoleon reconsidering his career choice…

Industrial vs. Mom and Pop

First, it’s important to distinguish factory farming from family and hobby farming. Our romanticized image of agrarian animal husbandry still exists. I bottle fed calves as a teenager in the 90s. My wife’s family once raised a pig. Thousands of preparedness-minded suburbanites built luxury chicken coups at the outset of COVID. These examples aren’t what case 1 is targeting.

Factory farmed pigs are kept in industrial buildings on concrete floors, separated from their mother shortly after birth, and given little opportunity for interaction or mental stimulation. Despite what the entitled dogs in Babe may say, pigs are famously smart, as smart as or smarter than canines. Imagine thousands of bright Australian Shepherds, eager to herd and frolic and fetch, instead confined to concrete cells. Now imagine equally intelligent pigs in the same predicament, no warm mud to wallow in, no landscape to explore.

As Napoleon Dynamite discovered, factory farmed chickens are crammed into cages so small they can’t even spread their wings. Imagine having a powerful instinctual drive to do something as simple as flapping, yet being smothered between a wire cage that cuts into your feet and fellow prisoners pecking at your face. For your entire life. Whether bred for poultry or eggs, factory farmed chickens lead pretty miserable lives.

This just scratches the surface. If you’re up for the full gory truth, PETA and similar organizations routinely send spies undercover to record how factory farms are run. So do some research – ensure your position on factory farms is based on a fair and accurate assessment of actual, current conditions. But just as we shouldn’t accept the myth that all farms are happy farms, we shouldn’t conclude all meat sources are equally tortured.

Bacon vs. Beef

While some factory farmed animals have it really bad, it would be a sweeping generalization to conclude all meat sources are severely mistreated.

Beef cattle, for example, often live a decent life up until the point of slaughter. They’re usually free to roam and graze, breed and birth, and are left largely to behave as they might in the wild. This isn’t because beef farmers are necessarily concerned with cows’ happiness. Giving them room to roam is simply efficient and convenient. Cattle need grass (and hay during the winter), a water source (any pond or creek will do), and a good enough fence. Fenced fields are cheap. Pond water falls freely from the sky. So long as you don’t have too many cows per acre, or you rotate the herd at regular intervals, grass grows on its own. I know because I live in cattle country and thanks to kind neighbors enjoy ATV rides along and through cow pastures regularly (watch for those patties!). Beef cattle aren’t pampered. But their lives usually aren’t as bad as factory farmed pigs and chickens.

Of course, veal’s another story. Veal comes from calves who have weights tied around their necks to prevent them from moving. This ensures their meat is tender and white, which is what makes veal veal.

Cows are also sometimes artificially inseminated rather than naturally bred. Having a farmer impregnate you with a long straw feels invasive, cow or not. Young bulls often have their testicles removed via a thick rubber band that cuts off the blood supply and causes the scrotum to rot and fall off (this turns bulls into steers, preferred because steers are less aggressive and easier to handle). The de-horning process is painful and traumatic. Horns are either prevented from growing with an acidic cream, or cut off with shears (horns look cool, but being gored isn’t).

So it’s not all green grass and loafing. But hey, cattle are largely left alone, receive water, food and medical attention, I’m assuming even at the largest operations. Simply being able to roam outdoors is worth a great deal, and so beef cattle in particular would seem to have a less miserable life than non-free range poultry chickens and laying hens, as well as factory farmed pigs.

We should also note that dairy (milk-producing) cows have it worse off than beef cattle. I know because I’ve visited local dairies – watched a high school buddy dip a cow’s udders in an iodine solution before attaching the suction mechanism that drained its milk. One hardship is that dairy cows are kept perpetually pregnant – that’s why they’re able to continually produce milk. Male offspring aren’t especially useful on a dairy farm, and are sold to be raised for beef. That’s how I obtained my own calves as a kid, by buying 3-day-old Holsteins from a local dairy which I’d then raise to 6 months or so and sell to farmers at auction.

I concede this so you know the extent and limits of my experience with farm animals. Full factory farms I know only through YouTube. But medium-sized beef cattle and dairy farms and hobby egg operations, I’ve seen up close. I actually raised chickens as a kid – my favorite’s name was Cluck. My first calf’s name was Buttercup. If your only encounters with farm animals have been at the zoo, do some research so your view isn’t based on an overly rosy or an overly ugly myth. The truth is somewhere in between.

Size Matters

Ethicist and philosophy grad school buddy Joel MacClellan once made a convincing argument that it’s less morally problematic to eat meat from large as opposed to small animals. Why? One cow can supplement a small family’s diet for an entire year. However, one chicken won’t last a week. In fact, if KFC’s family-sized buckets are any indication, sometimes it takes more than one chicken to feed a single family a single meal.

Assuming cows’ and chicken’ ‘lives and suffering matter equally, if killing and eating one rather than the other would decrease suffering and death, all else equal, that’s the one people should eat. In fact, if whale meat were healthy and sustainable, according to this line of argument, we should all switch to whale. Or bear or hippopotamus or whatever.

MacClellan’s insistence that we eat meat in ways that minimizes overall pain and maximizes overall pleasure is consistent with the argument Australian philosopher Peter Singer offers in Animal Liberation. A Utilitarian, Singer contrasts the pleasure humans get from the taste of animal flesh with the great suffering animals must endure to provide it, concluding that our pleasure is far outweighed by their pain. His logic is hard to deny.

Given that factory farms are especially miserable, Singer’s argument is most powerful for animals stuck in them, living under the worst conditions. And combined with MacClellan’s argument, it would seem that eating smaller animals, which presumably endure greater suffering to produce similar nutrition and taste satisfaction, is more morally problematic than eating larger animals.

Thus, a reasonable person interested in developing a nuanced position on factory farming might conclude that it’s less wrong to eat non-veal beef as opposed to chicken, bacon and other meats. Why? Because non-veal beef cattle’s lives aren’t as terrible, and each can provide many times more satisfaction and nutrition to those who consume them.

Of course, an even more reasonable person might insist that carnivores eat wild deer or salmon, or synthetic meats grown in a lab (wait, wasn’t that an ethics bowl case from last season?). And an even more reasonable person might insist we satisfy our taste buds with yummy fruits and vegetables, and get our nutrition from pain-free plant-based proteins. But if your team isn’t ready for all that, try pitching this approach. And whatever the case, base your views on a realistic assessment of what factory farming is all about.

P.S. Australian Ethics Olympiad coach Andre Costantino wrote this excellent post on the ethics of meat consumption only two months ago. It’s on a different ethics bowl case, and not specific to factory farming. But it does address common misconceptions and bad rationalizations likely to come up during prep and/or competition.

P.P.S. Notice how the analysis above steers the conversation away from traditional factory farming, and also how it doesn’t directly address the enumerated list of harms found in the case’s final paragraph. To thoroughly prepare your team, be sure they’re ready to answer the question asked (oh man, practice question 3 with this one is tough!) , and also have some thoughts on the issues raised in the case which include environmental harms, labor-related issues, the fact that meat-eating is often unhealthy, and how large factory farms run smaller operations out of business.